1

Bartosz Stopel

Aesthetic Appreciation and the Dependence Between Deep and Surface Interpretation

(Abstract)

Full-length article in: JLT 14/1 (2020), 94–119.

The article traces the relationship between what is called surface, aesthetic interpretation and deep, semantic, theory-driven interpretation of literature. The former is identified with how interpretation is typically understood in analytic philosophy of art, whereas the latter as belonging to continental literary theory, thus framing the discussion within the relevant debates that the two eminent philosophical schools engage in. Specifically, the article argues in favor of a number of claims. It discusses the notion of surface interpretation, understood as the informed practice involved in general attention to a literary work with an aim of attaining an aesthetically rewarding experience (appreciation). Surface interpretation locates a literary work in a specific art-historical context and at minimum acknowledges the author’s categorial intentions pertinent to genre, general aims and representational content of the work. The article also argues against the notion that appreciation, which is supposed to be the main aim of surface interpretation, is purely perceptual (Carroll, Lamarque) and that consequently aesthetic experience does not involve affective experiences. Grounding appreciation in affective experiences (Levinson) leads me to acknowledge an important continuity between fully formed aesthetic experience and more instinctive or »effortless« ways of attending to a work, such as when one »just enjoys« the emotions afforded by, say, a horror story rather than with full aesthetic attention to the work, where the affective component dominates, but which are less structured to be properly called aesthetic within the conceptual framework I offer here. As a result, I divide the pleasures of attending to an artwork into the instinctive, hedonic ones and the properly aesthetic ones, which both constitute two basic modes of reading. The aesthetic mode is not fully separate from the hedonic one, but on the contrary, by tapping directly into the hardwired human cognitive-affective architecture, it provides a general framework and parameters for the emergence of the higher-order aesthetic mode where more prominence is given to art-historical knowledge and more attention to the design and form/content interrelation. Importantly, aesthetic mode does not operate with the absence of the hedonic one, though they can simultaneously produce different evaluations (e. g. hedonically positive, aesthetically/artistically negative). The two modes could be said to have distinct model readers with corresponding levels of competence. The hedonic reader, as opposed to the aesthetic one, would be largely oblivious to art-historical contexts and would be more selective in terms of attention to the work, relying on direct affect-triggering textual cues. Interpretive effort would be reduced, too. I also discuss my model with reference to the psycho-historical framework for the study of art appreciation as developed by Bullot and Reber which attempts to explain how art responders acquire more complex types of attention to the work, or stances, from mere exposure to the work’s perceptual content to tracing causal history and integrating historical contexts into a more rounded approach to art appreciation. An important part of my argument is the indication that non-habitual pattern isolation responsible for identifying structures, interrelations between a work’s elements and forming predictions about its development in the process of reading is a crucial component of aesthetic experience. Next, I move on to discuss deep interpretation, which typically is seen as miles apart from aesthetic interpretation. It is sometimes assumed that deep, semantic interpretation disregards surface interpretation, including authorial intentions and art-historical contexts and emphasizes reader’s active, playful role in generating an unconstrained swirl of connotations. Such a practice is seen either as being a source of bliss (Barthes) or as a purely intellectual pursuit attempting at enhancing the understanding of the work (Sontag). I argue against all three views and integrate deep interpretation into the model sketched so far. Seeing deep interpretation as unconstrained and purposeless (Lamarque) is an uncharitable straw man. Such a vision would render semantic interpretation unintelligible and random, but this is not the case. By looking into some examples taken from Roland Barthes’ own work which is one of the foundations of modern theory-driven interpretation, I argue that despite his bombastic claims, he is unable to start his deep interpretation project without acknowledging categorial intentions and art-historical context of the work’s creation. Consequently, and comparing his views to contemporary debates on work, authorship, intentions and aesthetics, his work is an attack on a rather dated understanding of these concepts. Theory-driven interpretation can be flawed or stretched, if it does not pay its dues to surface interpretation. Next, I argue that both surface and deep interpretation operate according to the principles of value-maximization (Davies) which can override author’s intentions about the details of her work’s meaning. Using a specific theoretical framework in deep interpretation is an extension of the non-habitual patterns isolation principle and serves to enhance the experience of the work by trying to recognize more pattern that add up to the work’s complexity while remaining faithful to the work’s basic contents. Taking up the semantic reading stance already entails taking up the underlying aesthetic and, more distantly, hedonic stances. In the end, theory-driven interpretation forms the third reading mode which emerges with a correspondingly more competent model reader from the partly-constraining aesthetic mode.

References

Barthes, Roland, S/Z. An Essay, transl. by Richard Miller, London 1974.

Barthes, Roland, The Pleasure of the Text, transl. by Richard Miller, New York 1975.

Barthes, Roland, Death of the Author, in: R.B., Image, Music, Text. Essays, transl. by Stephen Heath, London 1977, 142–149 (Barthes 1977a).

Barthes, Roland, From Text to Work, in: R.B., Image, Music, Text. Essays, transl. by Stephen Heath, London 1977, 155–165 (Barthes 1977b).

Brand, Peg/Myles Brand, Surface and Deep Interpretation, in: Mark Rollins (ed.), Danto and his Critics [1993], Malden, MA/Oxford ²2012, 69–84.

Bullot, Nicholas J./Rolf Reber, The Artful Mind Meets Art History. Toward a Psycho-Historical Framework for the Science of Art Appreciation, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36:2 (2013), 123–180.

Carroll, Noël, Aesthetic Experience. A Question of Content, in: Matthew Kieran (ed.), Contem- porary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, Malden, MA/Oxford 2006, 69–96.

Carroll, Noël, Art Appreciation, The Journal of Aesthetic Education 50:4 (2016), 1–14. Currie, Gregory, Interpretation and Objectivity, Mind 102:407 (1993), 413–428.

Danto, Arthur, The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art, New York 1986.

Davies, Stephen, Authors’ Intentions, Literary Interpretation, and Literary Value, British Journal of Aesthetics 46:3 (2006), 223–247.

Davies, Stephen, Philosophical Perspectives on Art, Oxford 2007.

Derrida, Jacques, Writing and Difference, transl. by Alan Bass, London 1980.

Feagin, Susan, Reading with Feeling. The Aesthetics of Appreciation, Ithaca, NY/London 1996. Feagin, Susan, Giving Emotions Their Due, British Journal of Aesthetics 50:1 (2010), 89–99. Foucault, Michel, What is an Author?, in: Paul Rabinow (ed.), The Foucault Reader, New York 1984, 101–120.

Goldman, Alan. H, Interpreting Art and Literature, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48:3 (1990), 204–214.

Hogan, Patrick Colm, Beauty and Sublimity. A Cognitive Aesthetics of Literature and the Arts, Cambridge 2016.

Keen, Suzanne, Empathy and the Novel, Oxford 2007.

Lamarque, Peter, The Death Of The Author. An Analytical Autopsy, British Journal of Aesthetics 30:4 (1990), 319–331.

Lamarque, Peter, The Philosophy of Literature, Oxford 2009.

Lamarque, Peter, Replies to Attridge, Blackburn, Feagin, and Harcourt, British Journal of Aesthet- ics 50:1 (2010), 99–106.

Levinson, Jerrold, Intention and Interpretation in Literature, in: J.L., The Pleasures of Aesthetics. Philosophical Essays, Basingstoke/London 1996.

Levinson, Jerrold, Toward an Adequate Conception of Aesthetic Experience, in: J.L., Aesthetic Pu suits. Essays in Philosophy of Art, Oxford 2017, 28–47.

Livingston, Paisley, From Text to Work, in: Nancy Easterlin/Barbara Riebling (eds.), After Post-Structuralism. Interdisciplinarity and Literary Theory, Evanston, IL 1993, 91–104.

Livingston, Paisley, From Work to Work, Philosophy and Literature 20:2 (1996), 436–454. Livingston, Paisley, Art and Intention. A Philosophical Study, Oxford 2005.

Livingston, Paisley, Authorial Intention and the Varieties of Intentionalism, in: Gary Hagberg/Walter Jost (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature, Oxford 2010, 401–419.

Nathan, Daniel O., Irony, Metaphor, and the Problem of Intention, in: Gary Iseminger (ed.), Intention and Interpretation, Philadelphia, PA 1992, 183–202.

Nehamas, Alexander, Writer, Text, Work, Author, in: Anthony J. Cascardi (ed.), Literature and the Question of Philosophy, Baltimore, MD 1987, 267–291.

Pettersson, Bo, Procrustean Beds and Strange Bedfellows. On Literary Value as Assigned by Lit- erary Theories, Journal of Literary Theory 2:1 (2008), 19–34.

Robinson, Jenefer, Deeper than Reason. Emotion and its Role in Literature, Music, and Art, Oxford 2005.

Ryan, Michael, Literary Theory. A Practical Introduction, Oxford 2007. Sontag, Susan, Against Interpretation and Other Essays, New York 1966. Tyson, Lois, Critical Theory Today. A User-Friendly Guide, New York 2006.

Vermeule, Blakey, Why do We Care About Literary Characters?, Baltimore, MD 2010. Zunshine, Lisa, Why We Read Fiction. Theory of Mind and the Novel, Columbus, OH 2006.

2020-04-11

JLTonline ISSN 1862-8990

Copyright © by the author. All rights reserved.
This work may be copied for non-profit educational use if proper credit is given to the author and JLTonline.
For other permission, please contact JLTonline.

How to cite this item:

Abstract of: Bartosz Stopel, Aesthetic Appreciation and the Dependence Between Deep and Surface Interpretation.

In: JLTonline (11.04.2020)

URL: http://www.jltonline.de/index.php/articles/article/view/1074/2475

A Persistent Identifier can be found in the PDF-Version of this article.